This is an extreme example to illustrate how to think about
personal income and how it relates to a worker’s productive output. Imagine
that agriculture becomes so automated over the next century or so that the
entire world’s output can be produced by pressing a single button. Yes, it’s
silly to imagine that the button-pressing could not be automated as well, but
bear with me. The entire world’s agricultural output can be done with a single
person who has no particular skills.
Think for a moment about our single button-pressing laborer.
How much does he earn? Should it be trillions of dollars, since he creates so
much of the world’s total value? He creates all of a necessary ingredient to a
functioning economy (and a living human species, for that matter). But that’s
not the right answer, because he’s easily replaceable. He is not uniquely
qualified. *Anyone* can push that button (for the sake of this example). So you
only need to pay him enough to attract him to that job. He needs to be paid
just as much as any other unskilled worker with a similarly difficult (which is
to say similarly easy) job. He’ll earn roughly what an unskilled landscaping
worker or dishwasher earns per unit of time worked, because the product of his
labor, though massive, would be produced whether we had him or not.
Hopefully this simple example points out that you can’t just
look at the value of the final product and claim that the worker produced it
all. You have to talk about a person’s *marginal* productivity, which is the
difference between what you’d get *with* vs *without* that person in the world.
A person’s income depends strongly on this, the marginal product of labor. In
no sense can you simply map a person’s labor onto a final product, determine
the value of that product, and thus quantify the worker’s contribution. In most
cases, some or most of that final product would be produced anyway by someone
else. In other cases (say, a CEO of a company who creates a truly novel product,
one that wouldn’t exist but for her/him), the final product would be
substantially different without that person.
Now we’ll change the example a bit. Suppose again that there
is a machine that produces all the agricultural output in the world, but it
requires quite a lot of skill to use. And there’s no upper-limit to this skill;
the very best “agriculture machine operator” in the world isn’t identical to
the median or 80th or 99th or even 99.99th
percentile. Suppose there is variation all the way to the top. There are so
many idiosyncrasies and complexities to running the agriculture machine that
you absolutely need the very best, very most productive person in the world to
do it. The relative value of the very best and the second best might be only a
1% difference in productivity, but that translates into tens of billions of
dollars. Humanity should be willing to pay something comparable to make sure
they attract the very best person to this job. If the very best machine
operator can produce $100 billion more in output each year than the second
best, then getting this person for a $50 billion annual salary is an absolute
steal.
In the simple button-pushing case, where an unskilled worker
can do the job and it’s nearly impossible to screw it up, humanity will be just
as well off if the current button-pusher ceased to be. In the other example, if
you don’t put the best guy in the world in that job, humanity really will be a
great deal worse off for it.
I’m not seeking to morally justify income inequality with
this post, although I personally think that income differences that are driven
by true productivity differences are perfectly fair in a moral sense. My goal with
this post is far less ambitious. I’m trying to get the reader to consider *why*
these big differentials in income exist. What is missing from many rants
against inequality is any *theory* about the determinants of income. You can’t
possibly know that something (like a person’s income, for example) is too high
or too low unless you have some kind of theory telling you what it should be. If
someone actually had such a theory, and it told them that everyone (at least
every identifiable class or sufficiently large grouping of people) earned
basically what the theory said they should earn, it would be a lot harder to
claim that inequality is a big problem. If someone’s theory tells them that,
say, farmers are underpaid but bankers are overpaid, then we can open up that
theory to scrutiny and see if it’s failing to capture something important. This
can be an enlightening exercise. It needs to take place.
World gdp = $75 trillion in nominal terms, $108 trillion in
real terms (adjusting for purchasing power). https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/List_of_countries_by_GDP_sector_composition
World Agriculture = 6.1% GDP https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Gross_world_product
World Agriculture = 4.5 Trillion in nominal terms, 6.5
Trillion in real terms.
But it’s kind of silly to talk about the “total” value of
agriculture. The first 90% is probably necessary for humanity to exist at its
current population. It's silly to talk about its "total value," which you might argue is infinite. The next 10% is worth quite a bit less than 1/9th
of the first 90%. This last 10% goes into making our food tastier (feeding cattle and making sugary snacks), not meeting our basic caloric needs. An additional 10% beyond what currently exists possibly has
negative value if you account for health issues related to overeating or the
costs associated with storing borderline-useless food and dumping spoiled food.
I acknowledge I am playing fast and loose with the marginal value of food in my
post; if the extra food produced by Mr. Super Producer in the 4th
paragraph isn’t very valuable, then his compensation will obviously be less
than I imply above. Hopefully you can look past that and acknowledge the point
about the marginal product of labor. You can always change the example to
something that doesn’t have a steeply declining marginal value.
Another aside. The examples above describe a ridiculous amount
of productivity coming from a vanishingly small proportion of the population. These
scenarios are not absurdly far off, if you think in relative terms. Two hundred
years ago almost everyone in the United States was a farmer; today almost
nobody is. To a crude-but-relevant first approximation, the percent of the US
population who were farmers has gone from 100% to 0%. The developing world is
seeing dramatic economic growth, so presumably (I should say hopefully) they
will follow a similar trajectory, so that what’s true of the US will eventually
be true everywhere. The point here is that absurdly few people are now doing
the work of what used to be absurdly many people.
No comments:
Post a Comment